Political Philosophy
RATIONALISM
In epistemology and in its modern sense, rationalism is “any view appealing to reason as a source
of knowledge or justification”. In more technical terms, it is a method or a theory “in which the creation
of the truth is not sensory but intellectual and deductive”. Different degrees of emphasis on this method
or theory lead to a range of rationalist standpoints, from the moderation position “that reason has
precedence over other ways of acquiring knowledge” to the more extreme position that reason is “the
unique path to knowledge”. Given a pre-modern understanding of reason, rationalism is identical to
philosophy, the Socratic life of inquiry, or the zetetic (skeptical) clear interpretation of authority (open
to the underlying or essential cause of things as they appear to our sense of certainty). In recent decades,
Leo Strauss sought to revive “Classical Political Rationalism should not be confused with rationality, not
with rationalization.
In politics, rationalism is a development of the Enlightenment that emphasizes a “politics of
reason” centered upon support of the concepts of rational choice, utilitarianism, secularism and irreligion;
this has especially been promoted by liberalism.
Background of Rationalism
Since the Enlightenment, rationalism is usually associated with the introduction of mathematical
methods into philosophy, as in Descartes Leibniz, and Spinoza. This is commonly called continental
rationalism, because it was predominant in the continental schools of Europe, whereas in Britain
empiricism dominated.
Rationalism is often contrasted with empiricism. Taken very broadly these views are not
mutually exclusive, since a philosopher can be both rationalist and empiricist. Taken to extremes the
empiricist view holds that all ideas come to us through experience, either through the external senses or
through such inner sensations as pain the gratification, and thus that knowledge is essentially based on
or derived from experience. At issue is the fundamental source of human knowledge, and the proper
techniques for verifying what we think we know.
Proponents of some varieties of rationalism argue that, starting with foundational basic principles,
like the axioms of geometry, one could deductively derive the rest of all possible knowledge. The
philosophers who held this view most clearly were Baruch Spinoza and Gottfried Leibniz, whose
attempts to grapple with the epistemological and metaphysical problems raised by Descartes led to a
development of the fundamental approach of rationalism. Both Spinoza and Leibniz asserted that, in
principle, all knowledge, including scientific knowledge, could be gained through the use of reason
alone, though they both observed that this was not possible in practice for human beings, except in
specific areas such as mathematics. On the other hand, Leibniz admitted in his book Monadology that
“we are all more Empirics in three fourths of our actions. Rationalism is predicting and explaining
behavior based on logic.
Philosophical usage
The distinction between rationalists and empiricists was drawn at a later period, and would not
have been recognized by the philosophers involved. Also, the distinction was not as clear-cut as in
sometimes suggested; for example, Descartes and Locke have similar views about the nature of human
ideas. The three main rationalists were all committed to the importance of empirical science, and in many
respects the empiricists were closer to Descartes in their methods and metaphysical theories than were
Spinoza and Leibniz.
History of Rationalism
René Descartes -)
Descartes thought that only knowledge and eternal truths – including the truths of mathematics,
and the epistemological and metaphysical foundations of the sciences – could be attained by reason
alone; other knowledge, the knowledge of physics, required experience of the world, aided by the
scientific method. He also argued that although dreams appear as real as sense experience, these dreams
cannot provide persons with knowledge. Also, since conscious sense experience can be the cause of
illusions, then sense experience can be doubtable. As a result, Descartes, deduced that a rational pursuit
of truth should doubt every belief about reality. He elaborated these beliefs in such works as Disclosure
on Method, Meditations on First Philosophy, and Principles of Philosophy. Descartes developed a
method to attain truths according to which nothing that cannot be recognized by the intellect (or reason)
can be classified as knowledge. These truths are gained “without any sensory experience”, according to
Descartes. Truths that are attained by reason are broken down into elements that intuition can grasp,
which, through a purely deductive process, will result in clear truths about reality.
Descartes therefore argued, as a result of his method, that reason alone determined knowledge,
and that this could be done independently of the senses. For instance, his famous dictum, cogito ergo
sum, is a conclusion reached a priori i.e. not through an inference from experience. This was, for
Descartes an irrefutable principle upon which to ground all form of other knowledge. Descartes posited
a metaphysical dualism, distinguishing between the substances of human body (“res extensa”) and the
mind or soul (“res cogitans”). This crucial distinction would be left unresolved and lead to what is
known as the mind-body problem, since the two substances in the Cartesian system are independent of
each other and irreducible.
Baruch Spinoza -)
The philosophy of Baruch Spinoza is a systematic, logical, rational philosophy developed in
seventeenth-century Europe. Spinoza’s philosophy is a system of ideas constructed upon basic building
blocks with an internal consistency with which Spinoza tried to answer life’s major questions and in
which he proposed that “God exists only philosophically”. He was heavily influenced by thinkers such
as Descartes, Euclid and Thomas Hobbes, as well as theologians in the Jewish philosophical tradition
such as Maimonides.(10) But his work was in many respects a departure from the Judeo-Christian
tradition. Many of Spinoza’s ideas continue to vex thinkers today and many of his principles, particularly
regarding the emotions, have implication for modern approaches to psychology. Even top thinkers have
found Spinoza’s “geometrical method” difficult to comprehend: Goethe admitted that he “could not
really understood what Spinoza was on about most of the time.” His magnum opus, Ethics, contains
unresolved obscurities and has a forbidding mathematical structure modeled on Euclid’s geometry.
Spinoza’s philosophy attracted believers such as Albert Einstein and much intellectual attention.
Gottfried Leibniz -)
Leibniz was the last of the great Rationalists who contributed heavily to other fields such as
mathematics. He did not develop his system, however, independently of these advances Leibniz rejected
Cartesian dualism and denied the existence of a material world. In Leibniz’s view there are infinitely
many simple substances, which he called “monads” (possibly taking the term from the work of Anne
Conway).
Leibniz developed his theory of monads in response of both Descartes and Spinoza. In rejecting
this response he was forced to arrive at his own solution. Monads are the fundamental unit of reality,
according to Leibniz, constituting both inanimate and animate things. These units of reality represent the
universe, though they are not subject to the laws of causality or space established harmony to account
for apparent causality in the world.
Immanuel Kant -)
Immanuel Kant started as a traditional rationalist, having studied the rationalists Leibniz and
Wolff, but after studying David Hume’s works, which “woke [him] from [his] dogmatic slumbers”, he
developed a distinctive and very influential rationalism of his own, which attempted to synthesize the
traditional rationalist and empiricist traditions.
Kant named his branch of epistemology Transcendental Idealism, and he first laid out these views
in his famous work The Critique of Pure Reason. In it he argued that there were fundamental problems
with both rationalist and empiricist dogma. To the rationalists he argued, broadly, that pure reason is
flawed when it goes beyond its limits and claims to know those things that are necessarily beyond the
realm of all possible experience: the existence of God, free will, and the immortality of the human soul.
Kant referred to these objects as “The Thing in Itself” and goes on to argue that their status as objects
beyond all possible experience by definition means we cannot know them. To the empiricist he argued
that while it is correct that experience is fundamentally necessary for human knowledge, reason is
necessary for processing the experience into coherent thought. He therefore concludes that both reason
and experience are necessary for human knowledge.
PRAGMATISM
Pragmatism is a philosophical tradition centered on the linking of practice and theory. It
describes ad process where theory is extracted from practice, and applied back to practice to form what
is called intelligent practice. Important positions characteristic of pragmatism include instrumentation,
radical empiricism, verificationism, conceptual relativity, and fallibilism. There is general consensus
among pragmatists that philosophy should take the methods and insights of modern science into account.
Charles Sanders Peirce (and his pragmatic maxim) deserves most of the credit for pragmatism, along
with later twentieth century contributors William James and John Dewey.
Pragmatism enjoyed renewed attention after W. V. O. Quine and Wilfrid Sellars used a revised
pragmatism to criticize logical positivism in the 1960s. Another brand of pragmatism, known sometimes
as neo-pragmatism, gained influence through Richard Rorty, the most influential of the late 20th-Century
pragmatists. Contemporary pragmatism may be broadly divided into a strict analytic tradition and a “neoclassical” pragmatism (such as Susan Haack) that adheres to the work of Pierce, James, and Dewey. The
word pragmatism derives from Greek πράγμα, (pragma) “deed, act”, which comes from πρήσσω
(prassō) “to pass over, to practice, to achieve”.
Pragmatism as a philosophical movement began in the United Sates in the 1870s. Its direction
was determined by The Metaphysical Club members Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, and
Chauncey Wright, as well as John Dewey and George Herbert Mead.
The first use in print of name pragmatism was in 1898 by James, who credited Peirce with coining
the term during the early 1870s. James regarded Peirce’s 1877-8 “Illustrations of the Logic of Science”
series (including “The Fixation of Belief”, 1877 and especially “How to Make Our Ideas Clear”, 1878)
as the foundation of pragmatism. Peirce in turn wrote in 1906 that Nicholas St. John Green had been
instrumental by emphasizing the importance of applying Alexander Bain’s definition of belief, which
was “that upon which a man is prepared to act.” Peirce wrote that “from this definition, pragmatism is
scarce more than a corollary: so that I am disposed to think of him as the grandfather of pragmatism.”
John Shook has said, “Chauncey Wright also deserves considerable credit, fro as both Peirce and James
recall, it was Wright who demanded a phenomenalist and fallibilist empiricism as an alternative to
rationalistic speculation.”
Inspiration for the various pragmatists included:
Francis Bacon who coined the saying ipsa scientia potestas est (“knowledge itself is power”)
David Hume for his naturalistic account of knowledge and action
Thomas Reid, for his direct realism
Immanuel Kant, for his idealism and from whom Peirce derives the name “pragmatism”
G. W. F. Hegel who introduced temporality into philosophy (Pinkard in Misak 2007)
J. S. Mill for his nominalism and empiricism
George Berkeley for his project to eliminate all unclear concepts from philosophy (Peirce 8:33)
Primacy of practice
Pragmatism is based on the premise that the human capability to theorize is necessary for
intelligent practice. Theory and practice are not separate spheres; rather theories and distinctions are tools
or maps for finding our way in the world. As John Dewey put it, there is no question of theory versus
practice but rather of intelligent practice versus uniformed practice.
Anti-reification of concepts and theories
Dewey, in The Quest For Certainty, criticized what he called “the philosophical fallacy”:
philosophers often take categories (such as the mental and the physical) for granted because they don’t
realize that these are merely nominal concepts that were invented to help solve specific problems. This
caused metaphysical and conceptual confusion. Various examples are the “ultimate Being” of Hegelian
philosophers, the belief in a “realm of value”, the idea that logic, because it is an abstraction from
concrete thought, has nothing to do with the act of concrete thinking, and so on. David I. Hildebrand
sums up the problem: “Perceptual inattention to the specific functions comprising inquiry led realists and
idealists alike to formulate accounts of knowledge that project the products of extensive abstraction back
onto experience” (Hildebrand 2003).
A summary of which can conclude that pragmatism is subjugated by perception.
Naturalism and anti-Cartesianism
From the outset, pragmatists wanted to reform philosophy and bring it more in line with the
scientific method as they understood it. They argued that idealist and realist philosophy has a tendency
to present human knowledge as something beyond what science could grasp. These philosophies then
restored either to a phenomenology inspired by Kant or to correspondence theories of knowledge and
truth. Pragmatists criticized the former for it’s a priorism, and the latter because it takes correspondence
as an unanalyzable fact. Pragmatism instead tries to explain, psychologically and biologically, how the
relation between knower and known ‘works’ in the world.
In 1868, C. S. Peirce argued that there is no power of intuition in the sense of a cognition
unconditioned by inference, and no power of introspection, intuitive or otherwise, and that awareness of
an internal world is by hypothetical inference from external facts. Introspection and intuition were staple
philosophical tools at least since Descartes. He argued that there is no absolutely first cognition in a
cognitive process; such a process has its beginning but can always be analyzed into finer cognitive stages.
That which we call introspection does not give privileged access to knowledge about the mind – the self
is a concept that is derived from our interaction with the external world and not the other way around
(De Waal 2005, pp. 7-10). At the same time he held persistently that pragmatism and epistemology in
general could not be derived from principles of psychology understood as a special science: what we do
think is too different from what we should think; in his “Illustration of the Logic of Science” series,
Pierce formulated both pragmatism and principles of statistics as aspects of scientific method in general.
This is an important point of disagreement with most other pragmatists, who advocate more thorough
naturalism and psychologism.
Richard Rorty expanded on these and other arguments in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature in
which he criticized attempts by many philosophers of science to carve out a space for epistemology that
is entirely unrelated to - and sometimes thought of a superior to - the empirical sciences. W. V. Quine,
instrumental in bringing naturalized epistemology back into favor with his essay Epistemology
Naturalized (Quine 1969), also criticized ‘traditional’ epistemology and its “Cartesian dream” of
absolute certainty. The dream, he argued, was impossible in practice as well as misguided in theory
because it separates epistemology from scientific inquiry.
Reconciliation of anti-skepticism and fallibilis
Hilary Putnam has suggested that the reconciliation of anti-skepticism and fallibilism is the
central goal of American pragmatism. Although all human knowledge is partial, with no ability to take
a ‘God-eye-view’, this does not necessitate a globalized skeptical attitude, a radical philosophical
skepticism (as distinguished from that which is called scientific skepticism). Peirce insisted that (1) in
reasoning, there is the presupposition, and at least the hope, that truth and the real are discoverable and
would be discovered, sooner or later but still inevitably, by investigation taken far enough, and (2)
contrary to Descartes’ famous and influential methodology in a Meditations on First Philosophy, doubt
cannot be feigned or created by verbal fiat so as to motivate fruitful inquiry, and much less can philosophy
begin in universal doubt. Doubt, like belief, requires justification. Genuine doubt irritates and inhibits,
in the sense that belief is that upon which one is prepared to act. It arises from confrontation with some
specific recalcitrant manner of fact (which Dewy called a ‘situation’), which unsettles our belief in some
specific proposition. Inquiry is then the rationality self-controlled process of attempting to return to a
settled state of belief about the matter. Note that anti-skepticism is a reaction to modern academic
skepticism in the wake of Descartes. The pragmatist insistence that all knowledge is tentative is actually
congenial to the older skeptical tradition.
Pragmatist theory of truth and epistemology
Pragmatism was not the first to apply evolution to theories of knowledge: Schopenhauer
advocated a biological idealism as what’s useful to an organism to believe might differ wildly from what
is true. Here knowledge and action are portrayed as two separate spheres with an absolute or
transcendental truth above and beyond any sort of inquiry organisms use to coper with life. Pragmatism
challenges this idealism by providing an “ecological” account of knowledge: inquiry is how organisms
can get a grip on their environment. Real and true are functional labels in inquiry and cannot be
understood outside of this context. It is not realist in a traditionally robust sense of realism (what Hilary
Putnam would later call metaphysical realism), but it is realist in how it acknowledges an external world
which must be dealt with.
Many of James’ best-turned phrases---truth’s cash value (James 1907, P. 200) and the true is only
the expedient in our way of thinking (James 1907, P. 222)--- were taken out of context and caricatured
in contemporary literature as representing the view where any idea with practical utility is true. William
James wrote:
It is high time to urge the use of a little imagination in philosophy. The unwillingness of some of
our critics to read any but the silliest of possible meanings into our statements is as discreditable to their
imaginations as anything I know in recent philosophic history. Schiller says the truth is that which
‘works’. Thereupon he is treated as one who limits verification to the lowest material utilities. Dewey
says truth is what gives ‘satisfaction’! He is treated as one who believes in calling everything true which,
if it were true, would be pleasant. (James 1907, p. 90)
In reality, James asserts, the theory is a great deal more subtle.
The role of belief in representing reality is widely debated in pragmatism. Is a belief valid when
it represents reality? Copying is one (and only one) genuine mode of knowing, (James they prove in
inquiry and in action? Is it only in the struggle of intelligent organisms with the surrounding environment
that beliefs acquire meaning? Does a belief only become true when it succeeds in this struggle? In
Pragmatism nothing practical or useful is held to be necessarily true, nor is anything which helps to
survive merely in the short term. For example, to believe my cheating spouse is faithful may help me
feel better now, but it is certainly not useful from a more long-term perspective because it doesn’t accord
with the facts (and is therefore not true).
Pragmatism in other fields of philosophy
While pragmatism started out simply as a criterion of meaning, it quickly expanded to become a
full-fledged epistemology with wide-ranging implications for the entire philosophical field. Pragmatists
who work in these fields share a common inspiration, but their work is diverse and there are no received
views.
Logic
Later in his life Schiller became famous for his attacks on logic in the textbook “Formal Logic.”
By then, Schiller’s pragmatism had become the nearest of any of the classical pragmatists to an ordinary
language philosophy. Schiller sought to undermine the very possibility of formal logic, by showing that
words only had meaning when used in an actual context. The least famous of Schiller’s main works was
the constructive sequel to his destructive book “Formal Logic.” In this sequel, “Logic for Use,” Schiller
attempted to construct a new logic to replace the formal logic that he had criticized in “Formal Logic”.
What he offers is something philosophers would recognize today as a logic covering the context of
discovery and the hypothetico-deductive method.
Whereas F. C. S. Schiller actually dismissed the possibility of formal logic, most pragmatists are
critical rather of its pretension to ultimate validity and see logic as one logical tool among others - or
perhaps, considering the multitude of formal logics, one set of tools among others. This is the view of C.
K. Lewis C. S. Peirce developed multiple methods for doing formal logic.
Stephen Toulmin’s The Uses of Argument inspired scholars in informal logic and rhetoric studies
(although it is actually an epistemological work).
Metaphysics
James and Dewey were empirical thinkers in the most straight forward fashion: experience is the
ultimate test and experience is what needs to be explained. They were dissatisfied with ordinary
empiricism because in the tradition dating from Hume, empiricists had a tendency to think of experience
as nothing more than individual sensations. To the pragmatists, this went against the spirit of empiricism:
we should try to explain all that is given in experience including connections and meaning, instead of
explaining them away and positing sense data as the ultimate reality. Radical empiricism, or Immediate
Empiricism in Dewey’s words, wants to give a place to meaning and value instead of explaining them
away as subjective additions to a world of whizzing atoms.
William James gives an interesting example of this philosophical shortcoming:
A young graduate began by saying that he had always taken for granted that when you entered a
philosophic classroom you had to open relations with a universe entirely distinct from the one you left
behind you in the street. The two were supposed, he said, to have so little to do with each other, that you
could not possibly occupy your mind with them at the same time. The world of concrete personal
experiences to which the street belongs is multitudinous beyond imagination, tangle, muddy, painful and
perplexed. The world to which you philosophy - professor introduces you is simple, clean and noble. The
contradictions of real life are absent from it […] In point of fact it is far less an account of this actual
world than a clear addition built upon it […] It is no explanation of our concrete universe (James 1907,
pp. 8-9).
F. C. S. Schiller’s first book, “Riddles for the Sphinx”, was published before he became aware of
the growing pragmatists movement taking place in America. In it, Schiller argues for a middle ground
between materialism and absolute metaphysics. The result of the split between these two explanatory
schemes that are comparable to what William James called tough-minded empiricism and tender-minded
rationalism, Schiller contends, is that mechanistic naturalism cannot make sense of the “higher” aspects
of our world (freewill, consciousness, purpose, universals and some would add (iod), while abstract
metaphysics cannot make sense of the “lower” aspects of our world (the imperfect, change, physicality).
While Schiller is vague about the exact sort of middle ground he is trying to establish, he suggests that
metaphysics is a tool that can aid inquiry, but that it is valuable only insofar as it actually dos help in
explanation.
In the second half of the twentieth century, Stephen Toulmin argued that the need to distinguish
between reality and appearance only arises within an explanatory scheme and therefore that there is no
point in asking what ‘ultimate reality’ consists of. More recently, a similar idea has been suggested by
the post analytical philosopher Daniel Dennett, who argues that anyone who wants to understand the
world has to adopt the intentional stance and acknowledge both the ‘syntactical’ aspects of reality (i.e.
whizzing atoms) and its emergent or ‘semantic’ properties (i.e. meaning and value).
Radical Empiricism gives interesting answers to questions about the limits of science if there are
any, the nature of meaning and value and the workability of reductionism. These questions feature
prominently in current debates about the relationship between religion and science, where it is often
assumed - most pragmatists would disagree - that science degrades everything that is meaningful into
‘merely’ physical phenomena.
Philosophy of mind
Both John Dewey in Experience and Nature (1929) and half a century later Richard Rorty in his
monumental Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979) argued that much of the debate about the
relation of the mind to be body results from conceptual confusions. They argue instead that there is no
needs of posit the mind or mind stuff as an ontological category.
Pragmatists disagree over whether philosophers ought to adopt a quietist or naturist stance toward
the mind-body problem. The former (Rorty among them) want to do away with the problem because they
believe it’s a psudo-problem, whereas the latter believe that is a meaningful empirical question.
Ethics
Pragmatism sees no fundamental difference between practical and theoretical reason, nor any
ontological difference between facts and values. Both facts and values have cognitive content: knowledge
is what we should believe, values are hypothesis about what is good in action. Pragmatist ethics is broadly
humanist because it sees no ultimate test of morality beyond what matters for us as humans. Good values
are those for which we have good reasons, viz. the Good Reasons approach. The pragmatist formulation
pre-dates those of other philosophers who have stressed important similarities between values and facts
such as Jerome Schneewind and John Searle.
William James’ contribution to ethics, as laid out in his essay. The Will to Believe has often been
misunderstood as a pleas for relativism or irrationality. On its own terms it argues that ethics always
involves a certain degree of trust or faith and that we cannot always wait for adequate proof when making
moral decisions.
Moral questions immediately present themselves as questions whose solution cannot wait for
suitable proof. A moral question is a question not of what sensibly exists, but of what is good, or would
be good if it did exist. […] A social organism of any sort whatever, large or small, will simultaneously
do theirs. Wherever a desired result is achieved by the co-operation of many independent persons, its
existence as a fact if a pure consequence of the percursive faith in one another of those immediately
concerned. A government, an army, a commercial system, a ship, a college, an athletic team, all exit on
this condition, without which not only is nothing achieved, but nothing is even attempted. (James 1896).
Of the classical pragmatists, John Dewey wrote most extensively about morality and democracy.
(Edel 1993) In his classic article Three Independent Factors in Morals (Dewey 1930), he tried to integrate
three philosophical perspective on morality; the right, the virtuous and the good. He held that while all
three provide meaningful ways to think about moral questions, the possibility of conflict among the three
elements cannot always be easily solved. (Anderson, SEP)
Dewey also criticized the dichotomy between means and ends which he saw as responsible for
the degradation of our everyday working lives and education, both conceived as merely a means to an
end. He stressed the need for meaningful labor and a conception of education that viewed it not as a
preparation for life but as life itself. (Dewey 2004 [1910] ch. 7: Dewey 1997 [ 1938], p. 47).
Dewey was opposed to other ethical philosophers of his time, notably the emotivism of Alfred
Ayer. Dewey envisioned the possibility of ethics as an experimental discipline, and thought values could
best be characterized not as feeling or imperatives, but as hypothesis about what actions will lead to
satisfactory results or what he termed consummatory experience. A further implication of this view is
the ethics is fallible undertaking, since human beings are frequently unable to know what would satisfy
them.
A recent pragmatist contribution to meta-ethics is Todd Lekan’s “Making Mortality” (Lekan
2003). Lekan argues that morality is a fallible but rational practice and that it has traditionally been
misconceived as based on theory or principles. Instead, he argues, theory and rules arise as tools to make
practice more intelligent.
Aesthetics
John Dewey’s Art as Experience, based on the William James lectures he delivered at Harvard,
was an attempt to show the integrity of art, culture and everyday experience. (Field, IEP) Art, for Dewey,
is or should be a part of everyone’s creative lives and not just the privilege of a select group of artists.
He also emphasizes that the audience is more than a passive recipient. Dewey’s treatment of art was a
move away from the transcendental approach to aesthetics in the wake of Immanuel Kant who
emphasized the unique character of art and the disinterested nature of aesthetic appreciation.
A notable contemporary pragmatist aesthetician is Joseph Margolis. He defines a work of art as
“a physically embodied, culturally emergent entity”, a human “utterance” that isn’t an ontological quirk
but in line with other human activity and culture in general. He emphasizes that works or art are complex
and difficult to fathom, and that no determinate interpretation can be given.
Philosophy of religion
Both Dewey and James investigated the role that religion can still play in contemporary society,
the former in A Common Faith and the latter in The Varieties of Religious Experience.
It should be noted, from a general point of view, that for William James something is true only
insofar as it works. Thus, the statement, for example, that prayer is heard may work on a psychological
level but (a) will not actually help to bring about the things you pray for (b) may be better explained by
referring to its soothing effect than by claiming prayers are actually hear. As such, pragmatism isn’t
antithetical to religion but it isn’t an apologetic for faith either.
Joseph Margolis, in Historied Thought, Constructed World (California, 1995), makes a
distinction between “existence” and “reality”. He suggests using the term “exists” only for those things
which adequately exhibit Peirce’s Secondness: things which offer brute physical resistance to our
movements. In this way, such things which affect us, like numbers, may be said to be “real”, though they
do not “exist”. Margolis suggests that God, in such is linguistic usage, might very well be “real”, causing
believers to act in such a way, but might not “exist”.
Analytical, neoclassical and neo-pragmatism
Neo-pragmatism is a broad contemporary category used for various thinkers, some of them
radically opposed to one another. The name neo-pragmatist signifies that the thinkers in question
incorporate important insights of, and yet significantly diverge from the classical pragmatists. This
divergence may occur either in their philosophical methodology (many of them) are loyal to the analytic
tradition) or in actual conceptual formation (C. I. Lewis was very critical of Dewey, Richard Rorty
dislikes Peirce). Important analytical new-pragmatists include the aforementioned Lewis, W. V. O.
Quine, Donald Davison, Hilary Putnam and the early Richard Rorty. Brazilian social thinker Roberto
Unger advocates for a “radical pragmatism”, one that denaturalizes’ society and culture, and thus insists
that we can “transform the character of our relation to social and cultural worlds we inhabit rather than
just to change, little by little, the content of the arrangements and beliefs that comprise them.”[20] Stanley
Fish, the later Rotry and Jürgen Habermas are closer to continental thought.
Neoclassical pragmatism denotes those thinkers who consider themselves inheritors of the project
and the classical pragmatists. Sidney Hook and Susan Haack (kno0wn for the theory of foundherentism)
are well-known examples. Many pragmatist ideas (especially those of Peirce) find a natural expression
in the decision-theoretic reconstruction of epistemology pursued in the work of Isaac Levi. Nicholas
Rescher advocates his version of “methodical pragmatism” based on constructing pragmatic efficacy not
as a replacement for truths but as a means to its evidentiation.
Not all pragmatists are easily characterized. It is possible considering the advent of post-analytic
philosophy and the diversification of Anglo-American philosophy, the more philosophers will be
influenced by pragmatist thought without necessarily publicly committing themselves to that
philosophical school. Daniel Dennett, a student of Quine’s, falls into this category, as does Stephen
Toulmin, who arrived at his philosophical position via Wittgenstein, whom he calls “a pragmatist of a
sophisticated kind” (foreword for Dewey 1929 in the 1988 edition, p. xiii). Another example is Mark
Johnson whose embodied philosophy (Lakoff and Johnson 1999) shares its psychologism, direct realism
and anti-cartesianism with pragmatism. Conceptual pragmatism is theory of knowledge originating with
the work of the philosopher and logician Clarence Irving Lewis. The epistemology of conceptual
pragmatism was first formulated in the 1929 book Mind and the World Order. Outline of a Theory of
Knowledge.
‘French Pragmatism is attended with theorists like Bruno Latour, Michel Crozier and Luc
Boltnaski and Laurent Thevenot. It is often seen as opposed to structural problems connected to the
French Critical Theory of Pierce Bourdieu.
Legacy and contemporary relevance
In the twentieth century, the movements of logical positivism and ordinary language philosophy
have similarities with pragmatism. Like pragmatism, logical positivism provides a verification criterion
of meaning that is supposed to rid us of nonsense metaphysics. However, logical positivism doesn’t stress
action like pragmatism does. Furthermore, the pragmatists rarely used their maxim of meaning to rule
out all metaphysics as nonsense. Usually, pragmatism was put forth to correct metaphysical doctrines or
to construct empirically verifiable ones rather than to provide a wholesale rejection.
Ordinary language philosophy is closer to pragmatism rather than other philosophy of language
because of its nominalist character and because it takes the broader functioning of language in an
environment as its focus instead of investigating abstract relations between language and world.
Pragmatism has ties to process philosophy. Much of their work developed in dialogue with
process philosophers like Henri Bergson and Alfred North Whitehead, who aren’t usually considered
pragmatists because they differ so much on other points. (Douglas Browning et al. 1998, Rescher, SEP).
Behaviorism and functionalism in psychology and sociology also have ties to pragmatism, which
is not surprising considering that James and Dewey were both scholars of psychology and that Mead
became a sociologist.
Utilitarianism has some significant parallels to Pragmatism and John Stuart Mill exposed similar
values.
Influence of pragmatism in social sciences
Symbolic interactionism, a major perspective, within sociological social psychology, was derived
from pragmatism in the early 20th century, especially the work of George Herbert Mead and Charles
Cooley, as well as that Pierce and William James.
Increasing attention is being given to pragmatist epistemology in other branches of the social
sciences, which have struggled with divisive debates over the status of social scientific knowledge.
Enthusiasts suggest that pragmatism offers an approach which is both pluralist and practical.
Influence of pragmatism in public administration
The classical pragmatism of John Dewey, William James and Charles Sanders Peirce has
influenced research in the field of Public Administration. Scholars claim classical pragmatism had a
profound influence on the origin of the field of Public Administration. At the most basic level, public
administrators are responsible for making programs “work” in a pluralistic, problem-oriented
environment. Public administrators are also responsible of the day-to-day work with citizens. Dewey’s
participatory democracy can be applied in this environment. Dewey and James’ notion of theory as a
tool, helps administrators craft theories to resolve policy and administrative problems. Further, the birth
of American public administration coincides closely with the period of greatest influence of the classical
pragmatists.
Which pragmatism (classical pragmatism or neo-pragmatism) makes the most sense in public
administration has been the source of debate. The debate began when Patricia M. Shields introduced
Dewey’s notion of the Community of Inquiry. Hugh Miller objected to one element of the community
of inquiry (problematic situation, scientific attitude, participatory democracy